Recently, the Four Corners program on the ABC documented the
case of a young woman called Saxon Mullins and the man Luke Lazarus who was
convicted of raping her and then had his conviction overturned by on appeal on
the grounds that he genuinely believed she was consenting to intercourse.
This case highlights the problem with our rape laws as they
currently stand.
First of all let me say that the Appeal Court judge erred by exonerating the accused in this case. If the court had applied the
“reasonable man” test, Lazarus’s conviction would have stood. The “reasonable
man” test is a criterion often imposed in legal deliberations based on how a
reasonable person might be expected to act in a given circumstance. In this case,
although Mullins admitted she did not clearly and forcefully tell Lazarus to
stop, or could not recalling doing so, no reasonable person would have expected an 18 year
old woman who has never had sex, to want her first sexual experience to be on
her hands and knees in a filthy back alley being anally penetrated by a man she
had just met.
There is also the fact that Mullins admitted she had
consumed a fair number of drinks which suggests her ability to consent or to maintain
control of the situation was very likely to have been impaired. That is something that Lazarus also should have understood. Again, a reasonable man should have realised that, even
if she gave consent or appeared to be passively allowing intercourse to take
place, because she had been drinking, her judgement was likely to be impaired.
The appeal court’s decision in this case seems to relieve
the alleged rapist on any responsibility for ascertaining the state of mind of
the alleged victim or indeed having any due care for her overall welfare. Indeed there is very little clarity in Law as to what the
responsibilities of the man are (I am speaking of men having sex with women but
the discussion applies to any combination of sexes) in relation to determining
the state of mind of or the potential consequences for, the woman. For example does the man have to be convinced beyond
a reasonable doubt that the woman is consenting, or can he just make a decision on the balance of
probabilities. And how scrupulous is he supposed to be in making sure her
consent is not only informed but is not emanating from some state of impaired
judgement?
Furthermore, does the man have a responsibility for the welfare of the woman beyond the immediate situation? In the classical interpretation
of the crime of rape, apparently not. To put it crudely, the traditional rule
is if she allows it to happen, then it’s her fault, she bears the consequences.”
The problem is the crime of rape is a binary concept. An act
is either rape or not rape depending on whether there was consent or not consent. But the idea of consent itself is essentially an artefact of the legal
system. It fails to reflect the actual complexity and subtleties of sexual
encounters. Because a judge or a jury has to find the defendant guilty or not
guilty – which is a binary decision – the basis for that judgement, which is
consent, has also been configured as a binary concept.
But consent cannot be considered as a simple matter of yes
or no because it can be obtained in so many different ways. Consent can be
obtained through promises, payment, fear,
fraud or the deliberate impairment of judgement. Threatening someone with a gun or a knife can clearly
elicit consent. Intercourse with someone who is unconscious or disoriented by
drugs or alcohol to the extent that they are not aware of what is happening is also
not consensual and situations where a woman has sex with a man
thinking he is someone else also negates consent. So even under the traditional
tests, consent alone does not legitimise intercourse.
But those invalidations do not go far enough. Explicit
threats of violence or a visible weapon are not required to induce fear.
Fear can arise purely from the circumstances, from perceived or imagined
threats. It can arise from a psychological condition in the woman herself. That
fear might be unreasonable or unjustified but it still negates her consent.
If a court is prepared to give weight to the man’s subjective
assessment of whether the woman is consenting, surely the woman’s subjective
assessment of whether she is at risk must also be taken seriously.
To qualify all this let me explain that, in the late Sixties,
I was part of team of researchers at Melbourne University who conducted a
post-graduate study into the crime of rape. It was, at the time, one of the few
studies and ever done on the subject and certainly the most comprehensive study
done up to that time. One of the key findings of that study was that the
traditional definition of rape as being intercourse without consent was
inadequate and a recommendation was made that the crime itself would be better
abolished.
It was clear to us that, rather than a binary definition of
rape/not rape, there was a gradation between willing consensual sexual
intercourse and forcible sexual intercourse with violence or death threats. Between those
opposites lay a range of interactions and somewhere
along that line was a point where those interactions changed from acceptable to
unacceptable. It was the point where means of obtaining sex turned from
legitimate to illegitimate: where courtship became coercion, where seduction became harassment and inducement
became entrapment.
The suggestion of our report was that the crime of rape be replaced by a stature dealing with sexual
imposition or sexual coercion. Fifty years later, partly because of the campaign against sexual
harassment, that idea is finally starting to gain traction.
Traditionally the role of coercion has not carried sufficient
weight because there was a notion that women should resist rape even to the
point of dying rather than submitting to it. A woman who did not fight to the
death was thought of as having placed her life before her honour. That is not
so far from the situation in some countries where women are still imprisoned for
being raped but it is worth remembering that shades of that existed in
Australia as recently as about fifty years ago.
A reformed code of sexual violations would widen the concept
of unlawful sexual acts to include any situation where the ability of a person
to make choices that are free, informed and beneficial to themselves is impaired.
It would also impose clear responsibility on anyone instigating
a sexual encounter to make all reasonable efforts to ensure the encounter was the
result of an informed, uncoerced decision by the other party and further that there
be no detrimental consequences for that other person. Furthermore it would define
a criterion for establishing consent which would not be simply on the balance
of probabilities but that which is used for criminal trials themselves – beyond
a reasonable doubt.
There are many situations where consent is not so much invalidated as irrelevant. For example, a situation that people I know have experienced: a man offers to drive a woman home but instead drives her to a remote
location far out of town. She is given the choice of having sex or getting
out of the car. Historically, if the woman agrees to sex, the man is not guilty
of rape because he made no physical threats and the woman did have the option
of leaving. He is however guilty of creating a situation where, if the woman
does agree to have sex, or allow him to have sex with her, she is consenting to
an act that she would not have otherwise consented to. That is the key element
of coercion. In that situation, a court would traditionally have focussed on
the decision that she made and decided she made a free and informed choice to
have sex rather than walk twenty miles home. However that would be to focus on
the wrong issue. The issue is not what the woman decided: it is that she should not have been forced to make a
decision at all.
(Incidentally, it is surprising to me that Lazarus was not
charged with abduction since he told Mullins he was taking her to the “VIP”
room of the nightclub but actually took her out to the back alley. Lying to her
about where they were going makes it technically an abduction. It also goes to
establishing his intentions since that lie was clearly the first step towards engineering
a sexual encounter.)
Another case that is all too familiar is the situation where
a woman finds herself compelled to have sex with a man just to get him to
leave, or let her sleep. A man keeps a woman up all night till she is exhausted,
or won’t go home until the woman gives in and consents to sex. This is in fact
the literal meaning of harassment – to harry someone to the point of
exhaustion.
The fact is that woman can be coerced, blackmailed or tricked into having sex in a
number of ways that violate their autonomy but don’t technically qualify as
rape or even assault. They take the form of fraud, blackmail, extortion, beleaguerment, psychological manipulation and various forms of domination.
Domination, which appears to be the key factor in the Lazarus case, is one of the most common and most dangerous forms of sexual coercion or bullying but also the most likely not to be acknowledged as a form of coercion because of a long-standing notion that women find it erotic. Domination is the situation where the man does not become aggressive or threatening but becomes "masterful" giving orders and exerting control over the woman. Women, especially young women, are likely to find themselves with the man's instructions not because they are impressed by his masterfulness but because they simply don't know how to deal with the situation and regain their autonomy.
The main argument for replacing the crime of rape with general, graduated, crime of sexual coercion is that the acts which constitute sexual imposition - that is: extortion, blackmail, bullying, harassment, deception etc - are already illegal in other fields of human endeavour.
Many of the means that men use to obtain sex
from women are methods that would invalidate, for example, a sales contract. A
contract for the purchase of goods that was signed under duress, because of
exhaustion, or fear, or false promises would be quickly invalidated by a court. But, oddly, the same scrutiny is not applied to agreements for sexual activity.
The point is that the criminality in a sexual assault or any
other sex crime does not reside in the sex itself. The illegality lies in the
means that used to bring the act about. We accept that you cannot obtain goods
or money by deception, by coercion, by blackmail or by forcing people to make instant
decisions. That’s why we have cooling-off periods for all major purchases such
as houses and cars. The law recognises
that people can be confused by sales pitches and will commit to detrimental financial
deals that they later regret. In other words the law is prepared to protect us from our own decisions, even ones we made freely, or thought we were making freely, at the time.
Without wishing to trivialise of the Mullins/Lazarus case,
imagine that, instead of it being about a woman having sex with a man in an alley,
that Lazarus was a car salesman who had sold Saxon Mullins a car she didn’t want for an exorbitant price. Any court would
have annulled the sales contract saying, firstly, she was too young to enter
into such a contract, that in any case it clearly wasn’t the sort of car she wanted and
that he had taken advantage of her youth, inexperience and vulnerability to
sell her a car which was basically junk. His defence that he “sincerely believed
she wanted that car” would fall on deaf hears and he would be fined and
probably lose his dealer’s licence.
Surely a young woman’s dignity is more important than a car.
No comments:
Post a Comment